Next month, I will be going to Melbourne to
attend the annual conference of the Australasian Association for Continental Philosophers (I know, it sounds like something out of a David Lodge novel, but
it’s real). Continental philosophers are not people who think deeply about the
significance of living in a nation that’s also an entire continent. Nor, you
may be relieved to learn, are they sponsored by Continental Airlines (although
the concept of the “bar in the sky” developed by that company is somehow in keeping
with the spirit of many continental philosophy discussions).
Rather, the term “continental philosophy”
refers to philosophy from or inspired by thinkers from the continent of Europe,
which mainly means France, Germany and Italy. Even more importantly, it
designates philosophy that is NOT part of the (predominantly) Anglo-American
tradition of analytic thought. Somewhat confusingly, analytic philosophy is
said to originate with the work of a German philosopher, Gottlob Frege. It is
scientific in spirit, whereas continental philosophy is anchored in the methods
of textual interpretation and inquiry of the great religious, literary and
historical traditions that inform European culture. The split between the two
is a recent phenomenon, dating only from the Twentieth century, when the school
of analytic philosophy emerged.
Although (or perhaps because) their school
is a mere baby of the Western tradition, analytic philosophers tend to show a
fundamentalist, reformatory zeal, asserting that their approach to philosophy
is the one true way. As David Attenborough might have observed, had he ventured
into the jungle of contemporary academia, analytic philosophers will fight
fiercely to protect and expand their communal and material interests. Sociable,
loyal, even charming among their own kind,
they become territorial and dangerous in dealings with
philosophers from other schools, insisting that continental philosophy (which,
mind you, covers pretty much the whole tradition of Western philosophy before
the arrival of analytic philosophy) is not worthy of the title “philosophy” and
ought to be stamped out wherever possible. And indeed, it has proved close to possible
in many philosophy departments in Australia, the United States of America, and
the United Kingdom. Analytic philosophy is clearly in the ascendency in these
countries.
It should be admitted that most of the
philosophers grouped under the rubric of “continental philosophy” are secretly equally
dismissive of the value of analytic philosophy, considering that should it
magically disappear without trace, this would be no loss to the world. However,
they are much less organized or unified in their opposition to their natural
enemy, tending to be preoccupied with depressing problems of their own, such as
how to continue a tradition of thought which is implicated in the terrible
events of European history in the last century, particularly the Holocaust.
Busy deconstructing, critiquing, and declaring “states of exception” involving
the suspension of the authority of their own intellectual heritage,
continental philosophers have been in a weak position to withstand the energetic
and strategic advances of the analytic philosophers. While retaining a foothold in philosophy departments, they have tended to scatter into other
disciplines, such as literature, fine arts, cultural studies, and the social
sciences.
Hence the need for an Australasian Society for Continental Philosophy (ASCP), to bring the diaspora together. There is no
equivalent society for analytic philosophy. The analytic philosophers simply
dominate the Australasian Association of Philosophy.
This year, the ASCP conference has been
given the theme, “The Times of our Lives.” I am preparing a paper on Walter
Benjamin’s concept of Now-time. This is a suggestive understanding of
historical time, not as an empty, homogenous expanse in which events occur
sequentially, but rather as an intense experience of the present as a moment
that is full to overflowing with the past, to the point of catastrophe or possibly
redemptive revolution. To get a better sense of Benjamin’s work as a whole (his
oeuvre, to be continental about it),
I have been reading Howard Caygill, whose summary of Benjamin’s project goes
some way to explaining why continental philosophy is not in a stronger position
in contemporary academia:
Walter Benjamin |
“To a large extent Benjamin’s thought may
be understood as an attempt to extend the limits of experience treated within
philosophy to the point where the identity of philosophy itself is jeopardized.
In place of a philosophical mastery of experience, whether that of art, of
religion, of language or of the city, Benjamin allows experience to test the
limits of philosophy. The work of philosophical criticism according to the
‘method called nihilism’ allows experience to invade, evade and even ruin its
philosophical host.”
This is the kind of thing that makes
analytic philosophers see the work of continental thinkers as akin to a
parasitic disease. But to “allow experience to test the limits of
philosophy” need not amount to a suicidal flirtation with destructive forces.
In less melancholic mode, it might involve allowing experience to invite, lead
and even enliven its philosophical partner. But that would mean moving on from
the oppositional category of continental thought, and adopting the ‘method
called tango philosophy.’